What It Means to Be Human: A Philosopher’s Argument Against Solitary Confinement
by Maclyn WilliganThe degree of civilization in a society can be judged by entering its prisons. --Fyodor Dostoyevsky
In
recent years, resistance to the widespread use of solitary confinement
has gained significant traction in the United States. Opponents of the
practice have drawn upon everything from psychology and neuroscience to
criminology and economics to show the many harms caused by solitary.
Lisa Guenther, associate professor at Vanderbilt University and author of the new book Solitary Confinement: Social Death and Its Afterlives,
draws upon her knowledge of philosophy to make a thought-provoking
argument against the practice of isolating human beings for extended
periods of time.
Guenther
refers to the tenets of phenomenology, which deals primarily with the
development of the consciousness through first-person experiences—the
formative relationships we share with one another and the objects that
surround us. Solitary confinement, she argues, eliminates the
opportunity for incarcerated persons to form these meaningful
connections. Although the necessities of survival may be provided, those
held in solitary deteriorate nevertheless. She describes it as an
unhinging of the person’s psyche.
In an AEON Magazine
article, Guenther contests, “We do not exist as isolated individuals,”
but rather as constantly changing and adapting reflections of our living
environment. Phenomenology suggests that while we may believe ourselves
to have intrinsic characteristics unique to us, at heart we are
products of the environments we interact with on a day-to-day basis.
Solitary
confinement effectively removes all meaningful stimulus from prisoners’
environments, rendering them unable to ground themselves in a reality
created by sensory connections. Guenther, in an article published in the
New York Times, explains these sensory phenomena in simple terms:
Think about it: Every time I hear a sound and see another person look toward the origin of that sound, I receive an implicit confirmation that what I heard was something real, that it was not just my imagination playing tricks on me. Every time someone walks around the table rather than through it, I receive an unspoken, usually unremarkable, confirmation that the table exists, and that my own way of relating to tables is shared by others.
While
these may seem like insignificant interactions with one’s environment
to an average person, a phenomenologist would say that these are
reassuring occurrences that should not be taken for granted. Being
deprived of these interactions, as people in solitary confinement are,
leads them to question their reality and develop symptoms associated
with extreme isolation such as paranoia, hallucinations, and
introversion.
Five
Mualimm-ak, who spent a total of five years in solitary confinement
later reflected on the experience: “The very essence of life, I came to
learn during those seemingly endless days, is human contact, and the
affirmation of existence that comes with it.” Without these subtle yet
countless affirmations we experience daily, we too would have trouble
discerning what is grounded in reality and what is solely in our heads.
While
we don’t have to undergo this questioning of reality that individuals
subjected to solitary confinement must, we on the outside are not
unaffected by its practice. From a phenomenological standpoint, the
complete seclusion of these prisoners from our shared environments
restricts our capacity to understand the world in which we live.
Solitary confinement is purposefully concealed from the public eye—out
of sight, out of mind—and because of this we are denied the first-person
experience so important in forming our thoughts, feelings, and
judgments.
More
transparency in our prisons would allow the public to better understand
the treatment that isolated inmates undergo, and give them a greater
ability to critique and formulate alternatives to their practices. The
absence of isolated prisoners from our common consciousness perpetuates
their suffering and our ignorance, a dangerous combination.
Accepting
that humans are relational beings, Guenther suggests that the sensory
deprivation that people in solitary undergo is sufficient to unhinge
their minds. They are forced to question everything with which they
interact. And as they begin to reflect their morbid environment, they
lose their sense of what it means to be human.
This
phenomenological argument makes a strong case for the inclusion of
human contact in the list of fundamental human needs—and for the use of
solitary confinement to be seen as a violation of fundamental human
rights.
No comments:
Post a Comment